Hegel’s “Force and the Understanding” – Section Notes

Overview: “Force and the Understanding” is the third part of the Consciousness chapter in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. It continues the dialectic from Perception by introducing the concept of Force as the “unconditioned universal” that underlies appearances, leading eventually to the notion of Infinity and the transition to Self-Consciousness. Hegel examines how Understanding posits an unseen inner world behind the sensory world, and how this duality collapses into a single self-moving unity. Below, each paragraph is summarized and explained with key concepts, transitions, and commentary insights for clarity.

Paragraph 132: From Perception to the “Unconditioned Universal”

Summary: The failure of Perception leads consciousness to a new object: the unconditioned universal . This is the general essence that unifies the opposed moments found in perception . However, consciousness still treats this essence as an object distinct from itself. In Hegel’s words, the unconditioned universal “henceforward is the true object of consciousness,” yet consciousness “has not yet grasped its principle…qua notion” . In other words, consciousness has arrived at the idea of a conceptual unity behind phenomena, but does not realize this is its own thinking.

Key Points:

  • The object is no longer a mere “thing” with properties; it is a thought . Hegel calls it “unconditioned” because it isn’t dependent on a specific sensory instance .
  • Crucially, consciousness projects this unity outward as something existing in-itself, separate from consciousness. It does not recognize that this universal is a product of its own understanding. As one commentator puts it, “consciousness does not understand its own understanding as such” .
  • For us , it’s evident that the object’s character now reflects the structure of consciousness itself. But for consciousness, this new object still appears as an independent reality. Hegel notes that while the object has “become inherently and implicitly notion,” consciousness “does not know itself in that reflected object” . Consciousness remains “passive” here, taking the notion as an external truth.

Transition: Paragraph 132 sets the stage: the “thing” of perception has transformed into a pure concept . The task now is for consciousness to explicate this new object. The following paragraphs will develop what this unconditioned universal consists of and how consciousness experiences it.

Paragraph 133: The Notion as Object and the Role of Understanding

Summary: This paragraph emphasizes that the new object is a **notion ** which, however, appears to consciousness in the form of a being-in-itself . Consciousness “allows [this result] to have its way without knowing itself in it”, meaning the Understanding doesn’t see its own activity in producing this unity . Because the unconditioned universal arose from the breakdown of perception , consciousness is still observer, not creator. Any development of this notion seems to require an external impetus. Hegel indicates that it will be **our job ** to articulate the implications of this notion, since Understanding itself initially just “looks on” .

Key Points:

  • The object “is a notion, but without the form of being-for-self” – in other words, it is a concept implicitly, yet it appears as something that simply exists to be apprehended. The Understanding doesn’t recognize it as its own self-conscious concept.
  • Because this notion came about as a result of a dialectical collapse , the Understanding itself feels passive. Hegel says the result is not yet “for itself,” so consciousness “merely looks on and apprehends” the unfolding of the object as if it were a given process .
  • Hegel hints that **we ** must “step into its place and be the notion” to work out the content of this object . In other words, the philosopher explicates what Understanding itself cannot yet articulate. The goal will be to make the Understanding aware that the unity of the object is in fact a unity-for-consciousness.

Transition: With the notion of an unconditioned universal in hand, the next step is to determine its structure. Paragraph 133 suggests that the Understanding’s concept will need further development. Hegel will now “freely develop” the content of this notion of the object . This prepares us for the introduction of Force as the way Understanding makes sense of the unconditioned universal’s internal structure.

Paragraph 134: Unity of Being-for-Self and Being-for-Another – Content of the Unconditioned Universal

Summary: Hegel clarifies the content of the unconditioned universal: it is the unity of all the contradictory determinations that perception discovered. The object is defined negatively at first , but this negative result has a positive meaning: the object can only be genuine if it unifies being-for-itself and being-for-another . Thus, the new object is inherently a self-contradictory unity: an identity that contains difference within it . Hegel is saying that any true object must hold together the one-and-many aspects that earlier stood in opposition.

Key Points:

  • At the end of perception, consciousness “surrendered” all one-sided definitions of the thing . The thing is no longer defined by any single property or by abstract independence. The positive significance of this surrender is that only a unity of opposites is viable: the object is simultaneously a self-sufficient One and a relational Many.
  • Hegel calls this unity “the absolute opposites immediately posited as one and the same reality.” In simpler terms, what the object is in itself must also account for how it appears for another. The content can’t be split into two separate halves ; it must be a single essence that appears through differences.
  • Importantly, Hegel warns against thinking this is just a matter of “form” while some independent content still lies given. If we assumed the universal form is applied to some other given content, we would be back to the problem of perception . The content itself must obey the same unity: whatever the object is must also show the unity of self-sufficiency and relatedness. No purely “given” content can be exempt, otherwise the object would again have a dual nature . Thus, the unconditioned universal’s content is nothing besides the unity of for-self and for-another.

Transition: Having established that the object’s truth consists in this unity of opposites, Hegel now introduces Force as the concept that will capture how this unity operates. Paragraph 135 will mark the shift: since the unconditioned universal is still an object for consciousness, a distinction between content and form re-emerges in it. This leads directly to the concept of Force as the “content” that underlies the appearances.

Paragraph 135: The Emergence of Force – Form vs. Content and the Need for an Inner Distinction

Summary: In this pivotal paragraph, Hegel notes that because the unconditioned universal is still taken as an object, a difference reappears within it between form and content. The object as a whole is the true essence , but for consciousness it still has the “form” of being something out there. As a result, the object splits into two familiar aspects “in the shape of content”: a universal medium of stable elements , and a one reflected into itself . These correspond to the two moments of the thing we saw in perception, but now they are understood as moments of one essence . Hegel indicates that in truth these moments “do not lie apart” anymore but are “essentially self-cancelling aspects” that transition into each other . This unified essence, understood intellectually, is what Hegel calls Force.

Key Points:

  • The form/content split: Consciousness considers the unconditioned universal as an object, so it distinguishes what it is from how it appears to us . This yields the two aspects: a universal medium versus a unitary essence that pulls those matters together. These are essentially the “moments” of the object which Perception had identified , but now they are recognized as moments of a single content.
  • Hegel stresses that in the universal, these moments are not truly separate or fixed. Each moment inherently passes into the other: the “medium” dissolves the independence of each element , and the “unitary One” negates that independence by unifying them . We have a built-in tension: the universal medium and the unifying unity are “essentially self-canceling” – each implies and vanishes into the other .
  • This dynamic unity is what Hegel designates as Force. We are about to enter the analysis of “the play of Forces,” but here it’s introduced as “the shape which these moments take in the unconditioned universal” . In Jean Hyppolite’s words, “force makes sense only insofar as it manifests itself and posits what is inside itself outside itself; force is thus ‘the unity of itself and its externalization’.” . In other words, Force names the one essence that both withdraws into itself and expresses itself outwardly.

Transition: At line 87 of the text , Hegel actually inserts a new heading: “1. Force and the play of Forces.” This signals that we are moving into a new development. The next paragraphs will detail how Force operates through these two moments and how Understanding perceives a play of forces in the world of appearance. Essentially, we will see how the two sides of Force relate to each other and why Understanding needs the concept of Law to describe their unity.

Paragraph 136: Defining Force – The Two Moments

Summary: Hegel begins explicating Force by describing how the two aspects identified above behave. One moment of Force appears as the “universal medium” in which independent “matters” exist . Conversely, the other moment appears as the “unity” that cancels those differences – Force “driven back into itself,” which we can think of as Force proper. Crucially, Hegel notes that these two moments constantly pass into one another: the independent elements merge into unity, and that unity splits out into independent elements. “The elements set up as independent pass directly over into their unity, and their unity directly into its explicit diversity, and the latter back once again into the reduction to unity.” . This process is Force. He gives terminology: when force is in the form of dispersion into independent components, it is the expression of force; when it is withdrawn into a unity, it is force proper .

Key Points:

  • Force as a process, not a static thing: Force is defined by this movement of unity <-> diversity. The medium and the unity are not static states but phases that force continually cycles through . For example, think of a magnet: the one magnet is a unity that expresses itself in two poles ; the poles appear distinct, but they belong to one magnet and will reunite if the magnet is broken. The magnet’s “force” is the whole cycle of splitting into poles and being one magnet.
  • Necessity of expression: Hegel makes two important points about these moments: **** Force as unity must express itself – it cannot remain a mere inner without manifestation; **** in that expression, Force remains what it is – “in thus being within itself it is expression” . There is no actual force without its outward show. So the “inner” and “outer” of force are co-dependent.
  • Hegel’s description underscores that force contains a contradiction: it is at once the tranquil unity and the source of change. As Hyppolite highlighted, force is the unity of itself and its externalization. The Understanding conceives that behind all the changing appearances there is one abiding essence , but that essence only exists in generating those appearances. This idea will be vital as we see the “play of forces.”

Transition: At the end of ¶136, Hegel has distinguished Force in two guises but also hinted they are really one and the same process. Next, in ¶137, he will clarify that for Understanding these two moments initially look like a distinction in the thing rather than just a conceptual distinction. Thus begins the “play of forces” – the interaction of an expressing force and a counter-force – which Hegel will show to be another way of saying the same thing: one unified process.

Paragraph 137: The Unity of Both Moments – Force for Understanding

Summary: Hegel now reminds us that although we can conceptually distinguish the two moments of Force, in reality they form one immediate unity. It is the Understanding that posits them as different “sides” of a process. He says: “When we thus keep both moments in this immediate unity, it is Understanding, to which the conception of force belongs, that…carries the different moments qua different.” . In other words, the Understanding thinks of force as having an active side and a passive side. But in truth , “per se they are not to be different; the distinction exists only in thought” . Because the moments are only distinct in thought, what we had above was just the concept of force, not yet an actual experience of force.

However, Understanding now proceeds to picture force as a real substance with real differences. It “sets force free from thought” and posits an actual Force and actual “differences” as real entities . Essentially, Understanding conceives one force that is an independent unity and the expressions as another force . Thus we get the idea of two interacting forces: one force that is the “one” and another that is the “medium” of appearances. Force-as-unity is envisaged as an “excluding unit” and its unfolding appears as an other standing over against it .

Key Points:

  • Understanding’s perspective: Although the philosopher can see that expression and withdrawal are two moments of one process, the naive Understanding views them as two separate things: e.g. an active force here and another force there being affected. Hegel says understanding “puts forward [the moments] as substantial realities” . This is why in physics we talk about one force acting on another, etc.
  • Hegel is basically describing how consciousness will experience force phenomenally: it will seem like a play between two forces. For instance, imagine one magnet’s north pole repelling another magnet’s north pole – we might think of them as two forces interacting. Understanding’s category of force leads it to suppose an independent force on each side.
  • Interdependence implied: Hegel already hints that positing two independent forces is problematic. He notes that these supposed independent forces “would have no being at all if they had no subsistence” – i.e. force wouldn’t exist if not manifested in opposite ways . This means each “force” needs the other to manifest. As Hyppolite puts it: “When the two forces are posited in their independence, their interplay reveals their interdependence.” . So even as Understanding sets up two forces, the logic of the situation will show they are inseparable. Paragraphs 138–139 will demonstrate this interplay.

Transition: Now that Understanding conceives two distinct forces , Hegel will describe the interaction or play of these forces. In ¶138–139, he shows that when one force is posited as active and the other passive, they immediately swap roles – proving that the distinction is not a fixed one in the thing but only a product of thought. This dynamic will drive home the unity of force behind the appearance of two forces.

Paragraph 138: The “Soliciting” and “Solicited” Force – Reversing Roles

Summary: Hegel now examines one complete cycle of the interaction between two forces. He starts by taking one force as the active side: “Force, as reflected into itself , is one side… an excluding One. In virtue of this, the unfolding of the elements falls outside it as something other than it” . In other words, consider one force as an independent entity; the appearance of its effects seems to come from something outside it. We thus imagine a second force approaching it to “incite” it to express. Initially, force1 is a One-at-rest and force2 is an “other” that triggers it .

However, Hegel says in fact the first force has the other within itself from the start . So the very notion that an external other was needed is withdrawn. We “must drop the idea” that force is a one with an external inciter . Instead, force1 itself is the process: it externalizes into a medium. Thus what appeared as an external inciting factor is really just force1’s own outward aspect. Now force1 exists “as the medium of the differentiated elements” . But then notice: if force1 is now just the medium of appearances, where is the unity? The unity or oneness of force has seemingly moved outside – it now appears as something other than this spread-out medium. So we end up positing the unity as belonging to a second force which now becomes the “one” that attracts the elements back. Force2 “comes forward soliciting [force1] to reflect into self…cancelling its external expression” . In doing so, however, force2 is nothing but force1 coming back to itself. Effectively, the roles switched: what we called force1 became dispersion, and what we called force2 showed itself to be the unifying pull. But that unifying pull is the original force returning to itself. Hegel concludes: “The oneness [unity] vanishes as it appeared, viz. as something external; force is that very other – force thrust back into itself.” . In simpler terms, each side turned into the other.

Key Points:

  • Inciting vs. incited force: Hegel’s analysis shows the symmetry. If we label one force “inciter” and the other “incited,” this distinction doesn’t hold firm. The inciting force only appears to act externally, but it was incited by the other’s presence; and the incited force only reacts, but in doing so it incites the first. Hegel: “this distinction... turns also into one and the same reciprocal interchange of characteristics.” . Each force is inciter and incited in turn .
  • By the end of ¶138, it’s implied that what we really have is not two independent forces but one unified process appearing as a duality. The “other” that was thought to be separate was actually the same force in a different moment .
  • The result: the distinction between two forces collapses. Hegel says explicitly a bit later that the idea of two distinct forces “proves to be none; for it is the selfsame which repels itself, and this element repelled is essentially self-attracted ” . So the notion of an independent pair of forces is an illusion generated by treating the moments as separate.

Transition: Paragraph 139 will recap this result in more explicit terms. It will say that the “interplay” of the two forces consists precisely in each exchanging its character with the other. Through this movement, Understanding should realize that what is really there is one force manifesting under two aspects, rather than two separate forces. This prepares the way for the concept of a single Law that describes the behavior, replacing talk of forces as independent substances.

Paragraph 139: Complete Interchange – The Play of Forces as One Process

Summary: Hegel here explicitly describes the reciprocal interchange between the two forces. He notes that the interaction arises by assigning opposite roles to two forces, “whereby alone these determinations…have being.” . For example, assume Force A is the universal medium and Force B is the **one ** inciting it. But Force A is only a passive medium because Force B’s presence represses it; that means Force B actually gets its character from Force A’s being repressed. In fact, Force A in that scenario is the true cause making B an inciter ! Thus, “the former [A] gets the character it has only through the other [B]… and it loses this character…for it passes into the character of the other.” . In short, Force A and Force B swap characters: A was passive becomes active, B was active becomes passive. Each only is what it is by virtue of the other, and this “other” is immediately taking on the first character. This confirms that the distinction between two forces is not a real, enduring distinction – it’s a fluid, self-negating one.

Hegel concludes that there is “no longer any distinction of independently existing forces” after this complete exchange . All we have is one unified movement: a “complete exchange of their characteristics” where what is universal medium in one moment becomes negative unity in the next, and vice versa . The separate forces and their opposed qualities dissolve into a single continuum.

Key Points:

  • This paragraph solidifies the idea that each force contains its opposite. The inciting force contains the incited aspect , and the incited force contains the inciting aspect . Thus each force is “the opposite of itself” – a hallmark of Hegel’s concept of infinity .
  • Understanding’s initial view of two forces interacting has been undermined by the internal logic of that interaction. The “play of forces” turns out to be one process with a self-contradictory character . Hegel describes this as “a transition directly from one [force] to the other…Each of these two sides…has already passed into the other” .
  • This result is crucial: it means the Understanding cannot rest with the idea of multiple forces each with their own properties. Instead, the truth of this phenomenon must be expressed as a single underlying unity. We have effectively rediscovered the original “unconditioned universal” . Hegel is preparing us to say: what truly exists is Force as such governed by a Law that captures the relation of its moments. Indeed, he soon states, “The true nature of force thus remains merely the thought or idea of force…a unity which is not force withdrawn into itself…but is its notion as notion.” . That is pointing to Law or the concept of force.

Transition: The next paragraph will analyze the situation from another angle: the distinction between the content difference and the form difference is shown to be fundamentally the same distinction, which vanishes. By ¶141, Hegel will conclude that the outcome of the “play of forces” is that force’s true being is an unseen universal behind the scenes of appearance. In short, the Understanding is led to posit a supersensible world of law beyond the perceived flux.

Paragraph 140: Form- and Content-Distinctions Collapse

Summary: Hegel now clarifies that the interplay we just examined shows the collapse of both types of distinction that Understanding made: the distinction in content and the distinction in form . He notes that “they are, on the one hand, distinctions of content” , and “on the other hand, distinctions of form” . For us analyzing, it’s clear these distinctions were not real: the active side in form corresponded to what was content-wise the “repressed force,” and the passive side corresponded to the “universal medium” content . Each side was the same as its opposite when viewed from the other perspective . Thus, in the experience of consciousness, the extremes “are nothing per se” — their supposed distinct natures immediately transition into each other .

In essence, “the distinctions are…vanishing moments, an immediate transition of each into its opposite.” . The active = the inner unity = the repressed force, and the passive = the external medium = the expressed force; but those swapped, so neither determination stuck. The upshot is that force’s appearances have no enduring substantial differences at all. What is left? Hegel implies it is just the Notion of force itself that remains as the truth, since all particular manifestations prove to be ephemeral.

Key Points:

  • Content vs. Form: Hegel made a careful analysis: The content-distinction was mirrored by the form-distinction . Once we saw each force flip roles, it showed that separating content from form was untenable – the content “force” had the form of being incited at one moment and inciting the next, etc. So no stable content difference or form difference persisted .
  • This paragraph reinforces that any attempt to pin down two different forces or two different states fails. All that happened was a “vanishing” difference. We can say differences appear in the play of forces, but they are immediately negated. What persists is “difference as universal difference”, i.e. difference as such, abstracted from any particular forces . This is a very important move: the result of the play of forces is a **universal difference **, not particular independent entities.
  • By dismantling the independence of the two forces, Hegel has effectively shown that all there is is one force = the Notion of force. He prepares to state explicitly that the “resultant truth” of this whole process is the Law of Force – a stable universal that underlies the flux.

Transition: In the next paragraph, 141, Hegel will sum up the lesson: the concept of force becomes actual only as a duality, but that duality immediately collapses – therefore the true content is a simple law capturing the unity. We will see Hegel say that “force when actual exists wholly and only in its expression…and this…is nothing else than a process of cancelling itself” . Thus the notion of force is all that remains. This notion will be taken as the inner, supersensible truth – bringing Understanding to posit a “world of laws” behind the world of appearance.

Paragraph 141: Transition to Law – Force as Vanishing Appearance, Law as Essence

Summary: Hegel concludes the analysis of Force: “the notion of force becomes actual when resolved into two forces…But their being has purely the significance of disappearance.” . In other words, force is only realized as the interplay of two opposed moments, yet each moment immediately cancels out. Therefore, none of these opposed determinations has any independent reality. “They have no substances of their own which could support them…Force, when actual, exists wholly and only in its expression; and this…is a process of cancelling itself.” . The true essence of force thus remains the concept of force itself, the “thought” of force, not a particular force-being. The two moments “rush together into one single undivided unity…its notion qua notion” .

Hegel is saying that after this experience, Understanding sees that what is true is the unity itself, not the phenomena taken in isolation. The so-called forces dissolve into an “unconditioned universal” once again – now recognizable as a Law of appearance. In fact, Hegel explicitly states: “What is found in this flux of thoroughgoing change is merely difference as universal difference…It is the Law of Force.” . Thus the Understanding’s focus shifts: from talking about forces, it now talks about a law that governs how phenomena change.

Key Points:

  • Force exists only as its manifestation, which self-negates: This paradoxical nature means force itself is never a stable “thing” in experience – it appears only as a movement that returns to unity. Hence the enduring reality is not the movement but the law describing the movement. We have moved from an ontology of forces to an ontology of law.
  • Law as the “simple element” behind appearances: Hegel calls this universal difference “the ultimate simple element” of the play of forces . The chaotic exchange of properties condenses into a simple rule. For example, the play of north/south poles can be summarized by a law of magnetism . All the particular swaps are instances of one law.
  • Hegel emphasizes that this law is a “stable image of unstable appearance.” The supersensible truth is a calm unity corresponding to but standing above the changing sensible world. We see here Understanding’s new conviction: the supersensible inner world = the realm of laws that explain phenomena. This is the turning point where consciousness steps beyond immediate appearance and posits a hidden but intelligible world .

Transition: With the idea of Law, we enter a new phase. In paragraphs 142–143, Hegel will introduce explicitly the concept of the supersensible world – a world of laws that is the truth of the world of appearance. Understanding will now contrast the changing appearance with a permanent beyond . We are moving from the drama of forces to a more tranquil “kingdom of laws,” but this will raise new questions .

Paragraph 142: Appearance and the Supersensible World – Dual Perspective

Summary: Hegel now shifts to a higher-level view. He identifies two “universals” from the preceding: **** the first universal was the notion of understanding , and **** the second universal is the essence of force “revealed in-and-for-itself” – essentially, the Law as the true being . If we consider the first universal as the immediate object , the second is its negation or inner truth. Thus Hegel says, conversely, if the first universal was the immediate , then “this second has the character of being the negative of sensuously objective force: it is force in the form in which, in its true being, force exists merely as object for Understanding.” . In plainer terms, the second universal is the inner being of things purely for understanding – what things are in themselves , as opposed to how force appeared to the senses.

He further clarifies: “The first would be force withdrawn into itself, i.e. force as substance; the second, however, is the inner being of things qua inner, which is one and the same with the notion as notion.” . This signals that the second universal coincides entirely with the concept we derived – it’s the notion grasped as the true reality. We now have a picture of two levels: the world of appearance and a supersensible inner world of laws . Understanding effectively splits the world in two.

Key Points:

  • Hegel is making explicit the move to a dualist perspective: a world of sense vs. a world of thought. The sensuous play of forces was “negative” , so its truth is an intelligible world beyond sense. This beyond is “the inner being of things” identical to the notion of them .
  • He calls the first supersensible essence an “imperfect manifestation of Reason” – it’s basically the first time consciousness posits a rational order behind the chaos. It’s “imperfect” because it’s just a simple, static beyond at this point.
  • Another way to put it: force as it appeared was phenomena , whereas force as it truly is for understanding is the formula or law . The latter is “the same as the notion” – meaning the concept we arrived at through analysis now is taken as the actual reality .

Transition: Hegel now turns to discuss **Appearance ** and how understanding relates through it to the inner law. Paragraph 143 will describe appearance as the “mediating term” – a totality of phenomena that presents the law but is itself seen as mere appearance. We are basically entering the discussion of the “world of appearance” vs. the “supersensible world.”

Paragraph 143: Appearance as Mediator – The Totality of Seeming

Summary: Now Hegel defines what Appearance means in this context. Understanding does not have direct access to the inner truth; it relates to the inner world through the play of forces . He says: “Consciousness takes up a mediated relation to the inner; in the form of understanding it looks through the intervening play of forces into the true background of things.” . The play of forces, which we saw was self-cancelling, is now termed **Appearance ** – “for being which is per se straightway a non-being we call a show .” . It’s not mere illusion, but a “totality of seeming” that manifests the inner. Appearance is the entire set of phenomena viewed as vanishing moments that reveal a law. In it, the objects of perception “as they truly are” lie before consciousness: each determinate thing is seen as just a moment that instantly turns into its opposite . This flux is the development of the negative, but its true nature is the positive universal .

So, appearance is now understood as a process that “mediates” between consciousness and the supersensible inner world. Through the ever-changing phenomena, understanding infers the stable inner. Consciousness regards *the law * as the true reality, and the appearances as the “show” or representation of that reality. This means consciousness has effectively split its world: it has the inner essence on one side and the phenomenal show on the other. Yet it knows the two are connected .

Key Points:

  • Appearance defined: It is not “appearance” in the sense of a single phenomenon, but the entire dynamic display of phenomena considered as an unessential play that points to an essence. Hegel calls it “a totality of seeming ” and explicitly says it’s the reflection of the play of forces into itself .
  • For consciousness, appearance is now depreciated: it is “straightway non-being” – meaning it has no independent truth, only a vanishing existence to reveal the inner. This is a major shift from the start of Phenomenology . Now appearance is explicitly understood as *appearance-for-an-other *, not in-itself.
  • Mediation: Understanding views the movement of appearance as the middle term of a syllogism: one extreme is itself , the other extreme is the inner world, and appearance is the connecting process . The law is reached through the appearances.
  • Importantly, consciousness “is turned back upon itself as the truth” in this process . This foreshadows self-consciousness: the structure of the world now mirrors consciousness’ own thinking . However, consciousness does not yet realize that – it still projects the law into the object. It distinguishes the fact that it is comprehending from the inner content comprehended . So it still treats the inner world as an objective extreme, not recognizing it as its own conceptual construction.

Transition: Now that Understanding has established a realm of law vs. the realm of change , Hegel will explore the nature of this supersensible world of laws further. Paragraph 144 will explicitly introduce the idea of the supersensible world as the true world beyond the sensuous. Understanding initially takes this supersensible realm to be a static “kingdom of laws.” But there are further dialectics to unfold: e.g., there may be many laws , and the principle of change itself isn’t yet incorporated into the inner world. The concept of the “inverted world” will arise to address those issues.

Paragraph 144: The First Supersensible World – A Calm Realm of Laws

Summary: Hegel announces that within this inner truth , a “supersensible world” now opens up as the true world, lying beyond the sensuous world of appearance . The changing “Here and Now” of appearances is on this side , while the stable true world is an Beyond – an inherent reality that does not itself change . He describes it as “an immanent, inherent reality, which is the first and therefore imperfect manifestation of Reason – merely the pure element where the truth finds its abode.” . In simpler terms, the first supersensible world is just the collection of laws in their universality, a sort of static background which Reason has postulated. It’s “imperfect” because it has merely taken the form of a static beyond, without the principle of change that characterized the phenomena.

Thus, the “kingdom of laws” is born: Understanding populates the supersensible world with the laws corresponding to phenomena. For example, for various perceptual happenings , the supersensible world contains the Newtonian law of gravity. This world is “the true world” for consciousness now, and the sense-world is secondary. The opposition between these worlds is sharp: one is unchanging, essential, true, the other changing, inessential, apparent.

Key Points:

  • The supersensible world here is basically the conceptual world – it exists only for Understanding’s thought. Yet consciousness treats it as an objective realm .
  • Hegel calls it “the pure element where truth resides”: all particularities are stripped, leaving just a transparent universal. This is a big achievement of Understanding: it has an intelligible order of nature. However, by calling it “first, imperfect manifestation of Reason,” Hegel hints that this conception will need refinement .
  • Common sense analog: Think of the supersensible world as the set of physical laws, and the world of appearance as the actual physical events. At this stage, consciousness imagines the laws existing in a kind of quiescent state by themselves , while events happen here following those laws.
  • Dualism caution: Hegel is setting up the dualism only to sublate it. Right now, Understanding thinks the inner truth is entirely separate . Soon, issues with this view will force a deeper unity.

Transition: Next, in ¶145, Hegel uses an analogy of a syllogism to describe how understanding connects to the inner world via appearance . He will then begin to critique the “kingdom of laws” concept by pointing out it’s not yet the full story: there might be an indefinite multiplicity of laws, which conflicts with Reason’s demand for unity. This will push Understanding to seek a higher law or unity of laws and eventually lead to the idea of an “inverted world” to account for the principle of opposition itself.

Paragraph 145: Understanding’s Syllogism – Law, Appearance, Consciousness

Summary: Hegel briefly notes that the structure we have is like a **syllogism **: Understanding infers the inner world through the middle term of appearance . The “course of this inferential process” will further characterize what understanding finds in the inner world through the mediating play of forces . In simpler terms, consciousness now has a logical schema: Consciousness -> -> Inner Law. Hegel indicates that by following this mediation, understanding will gain experience of the relation between the worlds, and this experience will reveal new aspects of the inner world.

This paragraph is mostly a transitional framing. It tells us that explaining phenomena via laws is essentially the business of understanding , and that by doing so, understanding will learn from the process. The mention of “further characterization” hints that when understanding projects distinctions into the inner world via appearance, it might encounter contradictions or new distinctions it must account for. This is exactly what will happen: understanding will find that just positing a bunch of laws leaves something unresolved . That will generate a new law .

Key Points:

  • Hegel is basically saying: we’ve set up the terms , now let’s see the “experience understanding goes through regarding this relation.” . This foreshadows the dialectic ahead – understanding will put forward explanations, then refine them.
  • The syllogism idea underscores that the law is known only through its appearances, and conversely the appearances are interpreted only through a law. There is a dependence: no appearance, no content for law; no law, no meaning in appearance.
  • This mediation is still objective for understanding – it doesn’t see itself in it. But Hegel in the background sees that it is understanding itself connecting these moments. Eventually, this will feed into self-consciousness when consciousness realizes it’s essentially been talking to itself in the guise of explaining the world.

Transition: Now Hegel begins to refine the concept of law. Paragraph 146 will note that the inner world so far is a blank empty universal unless it gains content. Understanding initially finds it “empty” because it’s just the negation of all sensuous determinateness. This will raise the problem of knowability of the inner world and set the stage for giving it content via the manifold of appearances .

Paragraph 146: The Inner World as initially an “Empty Beyond”

Summary: Hegel points out that the inner supersensible world at first appears as a blank beyond – a pure universal with no specific content. “The inner world is so far for consciousness a bare and simple beyond, because consciousness does not as yet find itself in it. It is empty, for it is the nothingness of appearance, and positively the naked universal.” . This corresponds to the idea that if you strip away all the changing particulars, you’re left with an abstraction .

Hegel notes this situation is akin to those philosophies that claim “the inner being of things cannot be known.” – an obvious reference to Kant’s thing-in-itself or other skepticisms. In this stage, indeed, “there is no knowledge to be had of this inner world, as we have it here.” Not because our intellect is too weak, but because by definition an empty void yields nothing to know. If you define the true world merely as the negation of the sense-world, you end up with a contentless beyond . Hegel uses a vivid analogy: placing a blind man amid a rich world of color yields nothing for him; likewise, placing a seeing man in pure darkness yields nothing to see . An empty universal is equivalent to total darkness for understanding – no distinctions to grasp.

Hegel argues that if we stopped here, we’d be stuck with either clinging to the false phenomena or populating the void with our own imaginings . In fact, he says if we left the inner as a complete void , we’d inevitably fill it with “dreams” or subjective constructs . Understanding would “deserve no better” than daydreams, since it posited a truth with no content .

Thus, there is a necessity to give content to the supersensible world. The only source of content is the world of appearance itself. Hegel foreshadows: “If there were nothing more to be done with the inner sphere…then we would have to stop at the phenomenal world…Or…we would fill this empty void with daydreams produced by consciousness itself.” . But we won’t stop – instead, the content from appearances will be taken up into the inner. This means multiple determinate laws will populate the supersensible.

Key Points:

  • At this juncture, Understanding’s “true world” is like a form with no filling. It knows “there must be law” but hasn’t yet identified specific laws. This is unstable – consciousness craves determinate knowledge.
  • Hegel’s critique aligns with a known problem in philosophy: an absolutely unknowable reality is an empty notion. He is overcoming this by showing the inner is not truly unknowable – it must be understood through appearances.
  • Necessity of appearance for essence: The negativity of appearance gave rise to the concept of inner. Now the positivity of appearance is needed to give the inner articulation. Understanding must realize the supersensible has the content of the sensible, but in a transfigured form. This insight comes next: Hegel will claim “the supersensible is appearance qua appearance.”

Transition: Paragraph 147 is crucial: Hegel will resolve the emptiness by asserting that the supersensible is nothing other than the essence of the perceptual world itself – in other words, “the supersensible is appearance qua appearance” . This means the content of the supersensible is the very same content as the phenomena, but understood as lawful and non-independent. This realization will refute the idea of a totally separate second world and bring the content of appearance into the inner world .

Paragraph 147: The Supersensible is “Appearance Quâ Appearance”

Summary: Hegel resolves the issue by declaring that the supersensible world arises from appearance and in fact is appearance understood properly. “The supersensible is the established truth of the sensible and the perceptual. The truth of the sensible…lies in being appearance. The supersensible is then appearance qua appearance.” . This sentence is key: it means what the inner world contains is not some foreign beyond, but rather the essence of the sensory world itself considered as relational and not self-subsistent. We must be careful: by “appearance qua appearance,” he does not mean the supersensible is the same as the mere sensory world. He clarifies: we distort the meaning if we think the supersensible is therefore just the empirical world in another place . No – appearance as appearance means the sensible world sublated: grasped as a totality of vanishing interrelations, not as a collection of independent things.

He explains: commonly one might say “the supersensible is not the appearance.” But people who say that often mean by “appearance” the empirical world taken as real . That indeed is not the supersensible. But our meaning of appearance is precisely that those independent things proved to be mere moments. So, in our sense, the supersensible is the appearance – but considered in its truth . Essentially, the inner world now inherits all the content of the world of perception, only that content is understood differently . Thus, for every determinate aspect in appearances, there is a corresponding aspect in the inner .

Key Points:

  • This statement “the supersensible is appearance qua appearance” is a pinnacle of this section. It unites the two worlds: the beyond is not an other-worldly beyond – it’s the same world viewed in terms of its conceptual structure. The laws of the inner world are the distilled content of the outer world.
  • It also implicitly solves the Kantian unknowability issue: The inner being is knowable because it is nothing but the concept of the phenomenon. We know the law by analyzing phenomena .
  • Hegel warns against falling back into thinking of two separate worlds like two separate domains . That would be a relapse. Instead, the two are one reality: one appearance aspect, one essence aspect.
  • With this insight, understanding’s emptiness is filled: the supersensible world is now enriched with the specific differences in their essential form. We have a plurality of determinate laws each corresponding to some set of appearances.

Transition: Paragraph 148 will note that indeed now Understanding finds itself with determinate laws – but possibly many different laws. The inner world has “content” now, but as a plurality of laws each covering different aspects of appearance . This raises a new contradiction: understanding expects the truth to be one unified thing, not a patchwork of laws. So the multiplicity of laws is seen as a defect. Understanding will try to unify the many laws into a single higher law . This quest is the next step in the dialectic.

Paragraph 148: The Plurality of Laws and the Demand for Unity

Summary: Now that the inner world is populated with content , Understanding faces a new problem: there is an indeterminate plurality of laws. Hegel states: “Understanding finds itself in this position, that, for it, the inner world has come about only as the implicit universal without filling. The play of forces had only the negative significance…its only positive significance is as mediating agency, but outside understanding. The relation of understanding to the inner world through mediation is, however, its own process, by which the inner world will be found to receive fullness of content.” . This somewhat dense sentence recaps that we gave content to the inner world, and that content is present to understanding as a set of laws. Understanding’s process of explaining phenomena yielded these various laws as its product.

Hegel then notes the issue: The “kingdom of laws” is now a collection of specific laws, “but this plurality is itself a defect; it contradicts the principle of understanding, for which truth is inherently the universal unity.” . In other words, having many separate laws is unsatisfying to understanding’s drive for a single coherent truth. So understanding tries to reduce the many laws to one law. For example, it might unify the law of falling bodies and the law of planetary orbits into one gravitational law . However, when it does this, the specific content of those laws gets stripped away. The supposed “one law” ends up being very abstract – basically just stating that there is a constant relation . Hegel says this unified law “does not, in point of fact, express both kinds of laws” that it combined . It only expresses the concept of law in general . So instead of an actual richer unity, we get a “superficial” unity that loses explanatory power.

Hegel’s example: merging falling bodies and celestial motion yields the statement of universal attraction, which says everything has some constant pull on everything else . This is basically the form of a law but devoid of detail – it doesn’t tell you the actual forces without further specification. Understanding thinks it has the ultimate law of “everything attracts everything,” but this is just a tautological notion of law itself made into a statement . It indeed captures the formal unity of reality, but not its content. Understanding proudly declares reality is lawful as such, but finds that alone doesn’t predict actual phenomena.

Key Points:

  • Defect of plurality: If the inner truth were many distinct laws, it would reintroduce difference into the “truth” itself. Understanding wants a single coherent truth . This is a reasonable expectation: a patchwork of laws begs for a higher synthesis.
  • Attempted unification: Historically, science does seek unification . Hegel recognizes this impulse. But he notes a dialectical irony: pushing unity too far might empty the law of content.
  • Abstract vs. concrete law: The single law of universal attraction is an abstract universal – true in general, but empty of specifics. It’s basically an “law of law-hood.” As Brandom points out , understanding ends up merely finding “the concept of law itself” . It’s a bit like saying “everything is related somehow” – true but unenlightening.
  • Thus, understanding oscillates: many specific laws versus one unified law . This tension will propel the next development: understanding will discover that distinctions it tried to eliminate keep coming back. This will shift focus from trying to unify content externally to seeing an inner opposition within the law itself .

Transition: In ¶149, Hegel will reaffirm that the true outcome so far is the conception of the supersensible world as a “quiescent kingdom of laws” . But he’ll note this still hasn’t integrated the principle of change. The first supersensible world removed change to get stable laws, but now we realize change itself needs to be accounted for within the inner world. This sets the stage for a second supersensible world – the “inverted world” – which explicitly includes the law of change . Essentially, Understanding must formulate a law that captures the negative or self-opposed character of phenomena, not just a positive constant. That is coming with the “opposite law” and inverted world.

Paragraph 149: The “Realm of Laws” and the Need for an Opposite Law

Summary: Hegel describes the supersensible world at this point as “a tranquil kingdom of laws”, an “immovable copy” of the perceived world . It lies beyond perception yet is also present in perception as its stable order . This first supersensible world successfully got rid of the change and opposition that plagued perception – it presents an invariant structure. However, as we saw, this world of laws does not yet capture all of appearance. Specifically, “appearance continues to keep one aspect which is not in the inner world; i.e. appearance is not yet truly established as appearance, as that whose independent being has been done away with.” . The “defect” is that under various circumstances, the law looks different . The inner world doesn’t yet account for the variability itself – it only gives general rules for each context.

In Hegel’s terms: the law contains difference “in a merely universal indeterminate way” . But in reality, each law is a determinate one – so there are many. Understanding wants to see unity. It merges laws and ends up with an abstract “universal attraction” which expresses the bare concept of lawful relation but not the specific content .

So at the end of ¶149, we have: the supersensible world = realm of laws is recognized as an incomplete truth. It gives the general stable forms, but the richness of appearances isn’t fully reflected except as an indeterminate variety of laws. Thus, understanding is led to think beyond the first realm of laws. It conceives a notion of “law as such” , and thereby it implicitly considers something like the principle of “inner necessity” behind the laws . Hegel is hinting that the notion of necessity is arising.

In short, consciousness senses there must be a deeper law that governs why each law is as it is and how opposites are necessarily related. This deeper principle will be the focus of the next section: the inverted world, where the law of “like becoming unlike and unlike becoming like” is articulated .

Key Points:

  • The first supersensible world is static and plural – good for stability, bad for unity. It is the “copy” of the world of appearance, but lacking its movement.
  • The recognition that appearance is not yet fully accounted for means understanding must incorporate the principle of change/opposition into the inner truth itself. The inner must “reach out beyond” the first world and include what was left out.
  • The concept of Infinity is looming. Infinity, for Hegel, often means a unity that contains difference within itself . We will see that the next step integrates the idea that the true inner law is one of internal contradiction resolved – essentially the infinite structure where the like is unlike itself and vice versa.
  • Historically, one could think of this as moving from classical science’s static classifications to a dynamic notion . Hegel is preparing the metaphysical ground for the concept that **the true inner essence is not a peaceful “being” but a process **.

Transition: Now we move to the dramatic idea of the “Inverted World”. Paragraph 150–153 will step toward it by talking about the notion of force vs. law again and introducing inner necessity. But Hegel’s own structuring suggests by ¶157 he explicitly introduces the inverted supersensible world. We’ll follow the flow: Understanding will posit an opposite law to complement the first law . This yields the concept of a second supersensible realm that is the “inverse” of the first. Ultimately, these two realms will be understood as one – giving the structure of Infinity and leading to self-consciousness.

**

Paragraphs 150–153 : Indifference of Law and Force – Towards Inversion

(Hegel’s text here delves into how in the law the distinctions are treated as indifferent, whereas in force they were unified. He uses examples: in the law of motion, time and space appear independent, and gravity as a simple force is indifferent to that division . The key takeaway is that either the universal is indifferent to the parts in the law, or the parts are indifferent to each other . Understanding makes a distinction but simultaneously knows that distinction is not in the actual object – it’s a necessity of thought, a “verbal necessity” . So it “explains away” the distinction by saying force and law have the same content . This process of Explanation is basically the Understanding’s activity of positing an inner identical to the outer .)

In sum : Understanding in explaining phenomena says: “Here is the law, and behind it is a force which essentially has the same shape as the law – so really they’re identical.” This “distinction which is no distinction” is a tautology . Hegel calls it “an explanation that explains nothing”, where understanding essentially talks to itself . However, through this very process, something new emerges for consciousness: the “absolute unrest of pure self-movement” – i.e. the notion of an inner spontaneous alternating becomes object to understanding, at least implicitly . The process of explaining mirrored the play of forces – so Understanding was unknowingly reenacting the same unity-in-difference within itself.

By paragraph 155, Hegel notes that in explanation, consciousness was “in immediate communion with itself, enjoying itself only…occupied with something else, but in fact with itself” . This is the hint of self-consciousness emerging. But first, understanding must fully objectify this new insight: it must recognize a second law – the law of internal opposition. That second law is what Hegel now articulates as the law of the inverted world.

With that context, let’s proceed to paragraph 156 where Hegel formally introduces the idea of the “opposite law” – the law of like becoming unlike and unlike becoming like – which forms the content of the second supersensible world .

Paragraph 156: The Second Law – Like ↔ Unlike

Summary: Hegel writes that Understanding learns a new law from its experience: “that it is a law in the sphere of appearance for distinctions to come about which are no distinctions”. In other words, what is self-same becomes unlike itself, and what is different becomes the same . He calls this the “second law, whose content is the opposite of the first law” . The first law was an “invariable, self-identical difference” ; the second law says instead everything is in a process of switching into its opposite. “The like is unlike itself, and the unlike becomes like itself.” This expresses the kind of transformations we saw in the play of forces .

Hegel says the Notion demands that understanding hold both laws together and become conscious of their opposition . We now have two supersensible principles:

  1. Law of stable distinction: The identity of each thing with itself .
  2. Law of inverted distinction: The identity of each thing with its opposite .

Understanding initially treats this second law as another supersensible realm, an “opposite supersensible world” that is the inverse of the first . Hegel says: by means of this principle, the first kingdom of laws “has turned into its opposite” – each determination in the first is now seen to be the opposite of itself in the second . We thus get the idea of an “inverted world” : a supersensible domain where everything is the reverse of the way it is in the first domain. For example, where the first law says a particular thing is sweet, the second law would say that in itself it is sour ; what was north pole in the first becomes south pole in the other inner world , etc. Hegel even gives a moral example: the immediate law says revenge is satisfying, but the inverted law says in truth it leads to self-destruction .

So, Understanding posits two supersensible worlds: one a stable mirror of the phenomena, another an “inverted” mirror. This is essentially an attempt to incorporate the observed paradoxes by saying: “There is a second, deeper reality in which each phenomenon’s opposite is realized.” It’s like positing an anti-world where all our world’s laws are reversed.

Key Points:

  • The **second law ** is the culmination of the play-of-forces lesson: all determinate properties are inherently dialectical – they become their opposites under conditions. Understanding now makes that a law of essence itself.
  • The introduction of an “inverted supersensible world” is a dramatic conceptual move. Hyppolite notes: “The difference between essence and appearance has become absolute difference, with the result that we say anything in itself is the opposite of what it is for us.” . This captures understanding’s mindset: to save the idea of a stable essence, it splits it into two realms, treating the contradictory aspects as belonging to different worlds.
  • Hegel is not going to keep two separate worlds. Paragraph 159–160 will show that splitting them like that is unsustainable – instead, the two “worlds” collapse into one internally contradictory but unified world .
  • It’s significant that the content of the inverted world is not arbitrary – it is systematically inverted relative to the first. Hegel gives explicit pairings: sweet ↔ sour , positive pole ↔ negative pole, honor ↔ disgrace , etc. So the second world isn’t new content; it’s the first world’s content seen “with opposite sign.” This still reflects the point “supersensible = appearance as appearance,” just doubling it with a negation.

Transition: Paragraph 157 will formally state that through this principle, the first supersensible world has turned into its opposite – that each aspect is the opposite of itself. And paragraph 158 will define and illustrate the “inverted world” as such. After that, Hegel will resolve the duality, showing that the inverted world is not truly a separate world at all, but rather the same world looked at from the perspective of internal contradiction.

We proceed to see how Hegel dissolves the two-world dichotomy.

Paragraph 157: Each Side Becomes Its Opposite – Inner Distinction Itself

Summary: Hegel confirms that by introducing the inversion, “the changeless kingdom of laws…has turned round into its opposite.” In the first world, the law and its differences were taken as self-same . Now we establish “each side is, on the contrary, the opposite of itself. The self-identical repels itself from itself, and the self-discordant sets up to be self-same.” . In other words, any attribute or law from World1 gets an opposite attribute in World2, and anything inherently unstable in World1 is considered in World2 as stable in its opposite form.

Hegel then makes an important statement: “Only with a determination of this kind is distinction inner distinction, immanent distinction, when the like is unlike itself and the unlike like itself.” . This means we have finally an internal difference grasped as such – not an external other but a difference that resides within the thing . This is the concept of Infinity or self-contradiction that Hegel wanted to bring out. We now have distinction as an “internal” feature of the supersensible realm, not something that belonged only to appearance.

So at this point, Understanding has posited the structure needed: two opposite worlds to account for a self-opposed reality. But Hegel’s remark implies the two worlds are really one internally divided unity . It’s an “absolute distinction” now – meaning the distinction exists in the object’s essence itself . Yet it exists in this peculiar way: as a unity of opposites.

Key Points:

  • The talk of two worlds was basically a way for understanding to say “the essence differentiates itself.” By saying the essence world has an inverted counterpart, we’re really admitting the essence contains this contradiction inherently. We’re one step away from merging them.
  • Hegel is signaling that the true comprehension is to see both laws/worlds as one: “it is one and the same self-same which repels itself, and this repelled element is essentially self-attracted …the opposition set up is none.” . That was described already in the play of forces, and now at a higher conceptual level.
  • In modern terms, we might say the concept of a thing includes its opposite. For example, the concept of “north pole” implies a “south pole” within the same magnetic unity. The inverted world idea was a transitional image to reach this insight.

Transition: Next paragraph explicitly describes the inverted world and completes the picture with examples . Then 159 and 160 will collapse the two worlds. We’ll handle ¶158 with its illustrations and then the unification in ¶159–160.

Paragraph 158: Illustrations of the Inverted World

Summary: Hegel vividly illustrates the idea of the inverted world. He says: by the law of the inverted world, “the selfsame in the first world is the unlike of itself, and the unlike in the first is equally unlike to itself, or it becomes like itself.” . In concrete terms:

  • What by the first law was sweet is, in the inner inverted reality, sour .
  • What was white in the first world is black in the inverted world .
  • The north pole of a magnet, in the other supersensible inner world , becomes a south pole, and vice versa .
  • In electricity, what was an oxygen pole becomes a hydrogen pole in the other realm .
  • A more social example: by the immediate law, revenge on an enemy is the highest satisfaction of self . But the principle of the other world transmutes this into the opposite: such revenge in truth destroys the self . The law of the inverted world here would say the true satisfaction comes by renouncing revenge . In short, what seemed just becomes self-destructive, and what seemed destructive becomes saving.

Hegel concludes that if we turn this inversion itself into a law, we’d again have two opposed worlds: one where a given action yields disgrace, and another inverted realm where that same action yields honor .

In essence, Hegel is reinforcing the pattern: for every relation in the first world, the inverted world contains its opposite relation. “The punishment which, by the law of the former, disgraces a man…turns round in its inverted world into the pardoning grace which preserves his being and brings him to honor.” .

These examples drive home how radical the inversion principle is: it’s asserting that the truth of something is the opposite of its immediate appearance. But note, Hegel is not endorsing these as literally two coexisting worlds. He’s showing the Understanding’s way of imagining the inner contradiction: it imagines a separate realm where all is reversed.

Key Points:

  • The examples cover natural and moral phenomena. Hegel wants to show this pattern is general.
  • The scientific examples reflect how different reference-frames invert attributes . The moral example foreshadows the later dialectic of Lordship/Bondage and forgiveness in the Self-Consciousness and Spirit chapters .
  • For Understanding, it appears there are two realities: the world of how things immediately appear or are judged, and a second, hidden reality where the opposite valuations hold. This is essentially the extreme of the essence/appearance split – they are absolute opposites now.
  • Hyppolite notes this “absolute difference” is unstable . Hegel will soon collapse them, because keeping them separate undermines the whole point of discovering an inner necessity.

Transition: Having fleshed out the inverted world, Hegel in ¶159 will argue that we can’t really have two independent worlds like this. If we think of the inverted world as a separate sensible realm , we fall back into having two sets of things. Instead, the inversion must be understood as a single unified reality containing both sides. That leads to ¶160 where Hegel synthesizes them into the concept of Infinity: the self-contradictory unity. Let’s see ¶159–160 where Hegel dissolves the doubleness.

Paragraph 159: Collapse of the Two Worlds – Not Two Independent Realities

Summary: Hegel warns that if one imagines the inverted world as a separate physical or substantial realm, one ends up re-instating two separate worlds like before , which would be a regression . He says: “Looked at on the surface, the inverted world is the antithesis of the first, in the sense that it has the latter outside itself…and repels that world from itself as an inverted reality; that one is the sphere of appearance, while the other is the inherent being; one is the world as it is for another, the other the world as it is for itself.” . This is how Understanding initially posits it. But Hegel then says “such oppositions of inner and outer, appearance and supersensible, in the sense of two sorts of reality, are no longer to be found here.” . In other words, we should not think there are literally two separate ontological realms.

Why? Because if you treat, say, the sour thing as another actual thing apart from the sweet thing, you’ve just duplicated the phenomena on another level. “If the one element set up is a perceived reality, and its inherent being, as its inverted form, is at the same time a sensuously represented element, then sour is a real thing just as much as the latter – a sour thing; black is actual black; the north pole is the north pole of the same magnet; the oxygen pole is the given oxygen pole of the same pile.” . He’s pointing out that in those examples, the inverted attribute is always embodied in this world too . We haven’t found a new world – we just observed that each thing is connected to its opposite in this world.

Similarly for the moral case: the inverted “good intention” or “benefit to the criminal” is not another worldly event, it’s an aspect of interpreting the same action . The punishment that looks negative can be seen as positive – both aspects occur in our one world.

Thus, Hegel shows that the inverted world is not a second world beyond the first; it is the same world regarded under the law of internal contradiction. We should not split the substances. He emphasizes: “The differences repelled are not divided anew and assigned to two substances…One aspect would be the world of perception… and in opposition an inner world, just such a sensible world as the first, but in the sphere of ideas – one that could not be seen, heard, tasted, etc., and yet would be thought of as such a sensible world.” . That is exactly what we must avoid.

Key Points:

  • This is where Hegel criticizes any naive two-world metaphysics. The inversion principle is logical, not literal. The “other world” is not a ghostly duplicate of the sensory world; it is the sensory world’s conceptual structure.
  • We see how each inverted content was actually present in the phenomena: e.g., the magnet has both poles in one object, the act of punishment can be seen under opposite aspects. So there aren’t two separate magnets or two separate events – one thing embodies the opposition.
  • Hegel is effectively saying: the inversion happens within each thing, not between two things. Thus we have to conceive one world wherein each thing contains its own opposite.
  • Now, he is ready to articulate the concept of Infinity clearly, which he does in ¶160. Infinity will mean exactly that unity of one world with both laws present.

Transition: In ¶160, Hegel states this unity explicitly: the supersensible world “has in itself that other [the first world]; it is conscious of being inverted , i.e. it is the inverted form of itself; it is that world and its opposite in a single unity” . This is the final synthesis: one world with internal inversion – an infinite self-contradictory unity. We now summarize ¶160.

Paragraph 160: The One Unified Infinity – Self-Consciousness Awaits

Summary: Hegel resolves the two worlds into one by saying the distinction is purely internal now. “We must dissociate from the idea of inversion the sensuous idea of keeping distinctions fixed in a different element that sustains them; and set forth the absolute notion of distinction purely as inner distinction, self-repulsion of the selfsame as selfsame, and likeness of the unlike as unlike. We have to think pure flux, opposition within opposition itself, or contradiction.” . This is a mouthful, but it means: instead of picturing inversion as two separate existences, grasp it as one essence that differentiates itself internally – the like splitting into unlike, the unlike equating with itself. In short, think Contradiction as the fundamental structure.

He continues: “No doubt I put the opposite here and the other, of which it is the opposite, there…but just on that account, since I have the opposite by itself, it is the opposite of itself – it has the other within itself.” . This describes how isolating one side inevitably brings in the other internally. Thus, “the supersensible world, which is the inverted world, has at the same time gone beyond the other world and has it in itself; it is for itself conscious of being inverted, i.e. it is the inverted form of itself; it is that world itself and its opposite in a single unity.” . Here Hegel explicitly unites them: the inverted world contains the first world within it as its own opposite, so really there is one supersensible world that is aware of its own inversion. This is the concept of Infinity realized: “Only thus is it distinction as internal distinction…only thus is it in the form of Infinity.” .

Infinity for Hegel is not endless space or time, but the self-negating, self-restoring process“the selfsame repelling itself from itself and coming together with itself in its otherness.” We have that now: the supersensible unity is “itself and its opposite in one”.

At this achievement, Hegel says: “By means of infinity we see law attaining the form of inherent necessity, and so realizing its complete nature; and all moments of the sphere of appearance are thereby taken up into the inner realm.” . The inner world now truly contains the entire phenomenon and does so necessarily . The concept of inner necessity emerges when we see that opposite determinations imply each other within one substance. Nothing is left outside: the appearance’s flux is reflected inside as the unity of opposites.

Key Points:

  • This paragraph is dense but marks the culmination: The “absolute notion” is the recognition that difference = unity and unity = difference. This is Hegel’s famous identity of identity-and-difference structure.
  • The term “für sich verkehrte” implies self-consciousness: the world knows itself to be inverted. This metaphor presages that consciousness now effectively recognizes itself in the world structure – a step toward Self-Consciousness.
  • Indeed, immediately after, Hegel says that with infinity grasped, consciousness is essentially at the standpoint of Self-consciousness (as ¶163 will reflect: “consciousness is aware of it as what it is, consciousness is in this way Self-consciousness” ).
  • Infinity here is also called the “universal life” or “life-blood” of the world , emphasizing it as the living process underlying all stable things .

Transition: Hegel has thus completed the journey of “Understanding.” He discovered that in explaining the world, he was really talking about an infinite self-relating concept – which is a mirror of consciousness itself. In ¶162–163 , Hegel notes that what was missing in law has now come forward “as an object for consciousness” , and at that point “consciousness is in this way self-consciousness.” .

So, the outcome of Force and Understanding is that consciousness realizes the “object” it has been pursuing is in fact a reflection of itself . The satisfaction it got from explanation was because it was really communing with itself . This self-communing insight propels the transition to Self-Consciousness – where consciousness explicitly recognizes itself rather than an external object as the essence.

In summary, “Force and the Understanding” showed that the attempt to find the truth of objects leads to the concept of an internal self-differentiating unity – and that essentially points consciousness back to itself. The reading group can discuss how Hegel’s analysis of natural phenomena cunningly leads to a philosophical understanding of self-conscious mind, bridging nature and thought.

Commentary Notes: Robert Brandom interprets Hegel’s inverted world argument as showing the inadequacy of thinking of laws as hidden “superfacts” – instead we should see laws as inferential structures we impose . Jean Hyppolite emphasizes that force/inversion demonstrates that essence must include appearance’s dynamism – hence no rigid two-world split, but a single world of “the unity of itself and its externalization” . Ultimately, Hegel’s Force and Understanding teaches that what appears as external necessity is in truth internal necessity – a unity of opposites analogous to the way the Concept or the Self holds itself together through negating itself. This paves the way for the next part of the Phenomenology where Self-Consciousness takes center stage, explicitly grappling with the unity of subject and object that was implicit here.

Previous
Previous

Perception

Next
Next

Comparing the concept of Necessity across different theorists